Apportioning Responsibility in Tobacco
Cases As the tobacco companies' position becomes
increasingly indefensible, some commentators are still
asserting that the nicotine industry should be able to
maintain its immunity to liability claims by individuals.
The states may be able to sue successfully for their
tobacco-related Medicare costs, this argument goes. But
individuals should remain unsuccessful in the courts
because it has long been known that smoking is bad for
one's health, and people are responsible for their own
choices. This reasoning lets the tobacco companies too easily
off the moral and legal hook. Responsibility is not an all-or-nothing thing. The hit man is certainly responsible for the murder he
commits, but so is the guy who hired him. The rioters can be prosecuted for their mayhem, but
"incitement to riot" is also --rightly--
considered a crime. And when it comes to the use of deception and
manipulation to seduce others into making wrong choices,
we in the audience of Shakespeare's Othello think Othello
justified when, while also blaming himself for his unjust
killing of the fair Desdemona, he runs his sword through
and deceitful Iago. The tobacco company is in the position of Iago. For decades, the evidence increasingly reveals, it
worked to create false beliefs in people in order to
manipulate them into behavior that served the companies
even at the cost of the welfare of those making their
choices. It is only partly true that everyone "knew"
what they needed to know about tobacco and health to make
responsible choices. As with responsibility, so also is
knowing a matter of degree. True, there were scientific
studies and then warning labels on cigarette packs. But
there were also doubts, deliberately and deceptively
planted. And these doubts had effects on what people
"knew" and thus on the decisions they made. If there were no such effects, then what was the point
of the industry's spending so many millions disseminating
their lies? That whole campaign of deliberate
disinformation --about tobacco's addictive nature and its
health effects-- would have been a foolish waste of
money. And whatever else the tobacco honchos may be, they
are not fools when it comes to the spending and making of
their money. The tobacco industry's deception had effects, and
these effects hurt the people they deceived. We as a
society cannot afford to say that those who perpetrated
such destructive deception have no moral or legal
responsibility to those whom they willfully injured. Okay, you may say, so they are responsible, but if the smokers and the tobacco companies are both responsible, how do we handle the awards in suits in a situation as ambiguous as this? Do we just split the damages 50-50, or 25-75, or vice versa? Wouldn't any apportionment be arbitrary? Good questions, and I have a proposed answer. What is needed is that we make an assessment: by what
proportion would the sales of cigarettes in America have
been reduced if the tobacco industry had been honest
instead of deceitful about the health-related effects of
their products? Not an entirely easy question to answer,
perhaps, but an approximate judgment can be made. After
all, it turns out that the industry itself contemplated
taking the honest course, and rejected it because of
their calculations of how much business it would cost
them. Perhaps we can find their figures and use them. Once we have such an estimate, we can solve the
problem of apportionment. Whatever ----the proportion of
cigarette consumption that is the direct result of the
industry's deception, that can be taken as a good index
of how much of the damage done by cigarettes to people's
health can be laid at the door of the liars rather than
of those who were influenced by the lies when they chose
to smoke. That percentage, then, becomes the key to assessing
damages (other than punitive) for which tobacco companies
should be held liable by individual smokers. If the total
damages to an individual are $1 million, and the
deception is estimated to have boosted sales by 10%, the
company's responsibility is $100,000 in that case. In a morally sound society, people must pay the
consequences of their own bad decisions. But that
includes not only those who foolishly made
self-destructive choices. It also includes those who
selfishly --for their own profit-- manipulate other
people to do those foolish and self-destructive things. *Andrew Bard Schmookler is the author of Living Posthumously: Confronting the Loss of Vital Powers, just published by Henry Holt and Company. |